What does a bioethicist do?

It’s already been an intriguing question, one that came up a few times over the past year on ‘America’s Lifeline’. But now that President Obama has disbanded the President’s Council on Bioethics and instead, relies heavily on chief bioethicist Ezekial Emanuel, the debate within that community itself is getting very interesting. And listening to it, (or reading it), the picture emerges of an internal evolution of where the increasingly important field of bioethics is headed. And where Emanuel wants it to head.

Which isn’t where Arthur Caplan believes it should.

At its heart bioethics is an interdisciplinary activity and knowing how to work with others who do empirical, historical, legal and normative work is a must.

I had thought that advice to be sound until I heard Zeke Emanuel’s plenary address to open the most recent annual meeting of the American Society of Bioethics and the Humanities. Zeke espoused a vision for future bioethicists that I think is narrow, misguided and wrong. Now I say that in the spirit that Zeke himself enjoys–vigorous debate about a matter that both of us consider of the gravest importance.

Zeke Emanuel, a physician with a degree in political science as well, is one of the best and brightest scholars in the field of bioethics. His writings are solid and exemplify how best to integrate empirical inquiry with normative analysis. And the ‘shop’ he has run at the NIH Clinical Center for many years prior to moving into the Office of Budget and Management to work on health reform has done an outstanding job training younger scholars in the ins and outs of bioethical inquiry. These facts are precisely why Zeke’s recent plenary address to the American Society of Bioethics and the Humanities was so disappointing.

What did he say?

The only way for bioethics to flourish, to paraphrase Zeke’s key contention, is if bioethicists spend less time in public places, more time mastering quantitative methods and publishing empirically grounded research on topics such as informed consent and surrogate decision-making at the end-of-life in peer-reviewed journals.

And so on, as Caplan elaborates, until he says…

…let me try to point out why Zeke’s vision about what bioethics should be is severely myopic as well as inadequate.

This is clarifying.

Bioethics, in my view, has a duty to engage the public with bioethical questions. The topics that bioethics grapples with–how to manage dying, the use of reproductive technologies, what to do to maximize the supply of transplantable organs and tissues, how best to promote clinical and animal research, what information you should expect to receive as a patient about your diagnosis and treatment–are of keen importance and legitimate interest to everyone, rich and poor; young and old around the globe. Part, albeit part, but nonetheless a crucial part of the bioethicists role is to alert, engage and help to illuminate ethical problems and challenges both old and new in the health and life sciences. Note I do not say to solve them nor to be seen as an authoritative source to whom bioethical issues ought be assigned. Rather bioethics’ role is both Socratic and prophetic–challenge, probe, question, warn, chastise, alert, and, as Zeke appreciates, irritate the powers that be when necessary.

But now, Zeke is part of the powers that be, just about the highest official one, at that. He shouldn’t be discouraging that Socratic reasoning and challenging role we need bioethicists to carry out with vigor.

To engage in the public role that bioethics has and should enthusiastically continue to play in the media, policy, education, legislation and the law more tools are needed then empirical data no matter how rigorous or precise that data and the means used to generate it may be.

One must be able to present a cogent argument, know the areas of consensus that have been established about ethical issues over the history of medical ethics and bioethics, have a familiarity with health law, the infrastructure of policy and a grasp of political, cultural, literary, historical and social dimensions of what makes morality tick in various cultures. In the absence of these skills and knowledge data is completely and utterly blind, even useless.

In other words, as the title of this piece says, we need more than number crunchers.

For every ethical problem for which sufficient data exists to point toward an answer a hundred blossom for which the data don’t. For every ethical problem for which sufficient data have been assembled to make an answer rational, sensible, or even self-evident there are many where behavior, policy and practice do not and cannot be made to conform to that data. Sometimes data alone can point toward an answer. Almost always, however, it is a prior moral argument that points toward the use to which data will, could and ought be put whether that be in medical practice or in medical ethics. And more often then not moral and value arguments simply moot data and that situation cannot be rectified by appeals to more data.

This is the best I’ve seen out of Caplan yet. At the end of the argument, he’s the one who deserves an ovation. And all the attention this piece is evidently getting in the communications world Emanuel says is less important to bioethicists and the public they serve.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *